Chapter 3: Problem 3
Let \(\sigma^{s}\) be the Skolem form of \(\sigma\). Consider only sentences. (i) Show that \(\Gamma \cup\left\\{\sigma^{s}\right\\}\) is conservative over \(\Gamma \cup\\{\sigma\\}\). (ii) Put \(\Gamma^{s}=\left\\{\sigma^{s} \mid \sigma \in \Gamma\right\\}\). Show that for finite \(\Gamma, \Gamma^{s}\) is conservative over \(\Gamma\). (iii) Show that \(\Gamma^{s}\) is conservative over \(\Gamma\) for arbitrary \(\Gamma\).
Short Answer
Step by step solution
Understand the Concept of Skolemization
Proving Conservativity for Part (i)
Show Conservativity for Finite Set in Part (ii)
Extend Conservativity Proof to Arbitrary Set in Part (iii)
Unlock Step-by-Step Solutions & Ace Your Exams!
-
Full Textbook Solutions
Get detailed explanations and key concepts
-
Unlimited Al creation
Al flashcards, explanations, exams and more...
-
Ads-free access
To over 500 millions flashcards
-
Money-back guarantee
We refund you if you fail your exam.
Over 30 million students worldwide already upgrade their learning with Vaia!
Key Concepts
These are the key concepts you need to understand to accurately answer the question.
Conservativity in Logic
In the context of Skolemization, when we take a theory, say \( \Gamma \), and Skolemize it to form \( \Gamma^{s} \), conservativity ensures that \( \Gamma^{s} \) does not prove any new sentences that were not already consequences of \( \Gamma \).
- If \( \Gamma \) is consistent, meaning it has a model (or a way that all sentences in it can be true together), then \( \Gamma^{s} \) is also consistent.
- Every consequent of \( \Gamma^{s} \) is already a consequent of \( \Gamma \). So, even though we change the form, we don't change the logical consequences.
Satisfiability Preservation
When it comes to Skolemization, this transformation specifically focuses on eliminating existential quantifiers by adding functions. Importantly, Skolemization maintains the satisfiability of the original formulas - this means if the original formula is true in some interpretation, so is the Skolemized form.
- If \( \sigma \) has a model, \( \sigma^{s} \) will also have a model in a similar structure.
- This preservation is vital to ensure logical transformations don't break the initial condition of truth.
Compactness Theorem
In simpler language, as long as you can make smaller parts of your theory true, the whole theory can also be true. This theorem proves very useful when dealing with infinite theories.
- The theorem reassures us that if a formula holds for every part of a model, it holds for the whole.
- It helps in proving that if each finite subset of a Skolemized theory \( \Gamma^{s} \) is conservative over \( \Gamma \), then the whole theory is conservative.
Elimination of Existential Quantifiers
When you see a logical statement of the form "for every x, there exists a y...", the goal is to replace the existential part with a Skolem function.
- It helps in simplifying complex logical statements and eliminations. For example, turning \( \exists x \) into a function like \( f(y) \), removing the need for existential quantifiers.
- Elimination is crucial because it generally leads to simpler expressions easier to work with during logical derivations and proofs.