Chapter 11: Problem 15
Prove or disprove: If a relation is symmetric and transitive, then it is also reflexive.
Short Answer
Expert verified
The statement is false. A counterexample is the relation R = {(1,2), (2,1)} on the set A = {1, 2}, which is symmetric and transitive but not reflexive.
Step by step solution
01
Understand the Problem Statement
This exercise asks to prove or disprove whether a relation that is symmetric and transitive must also be reflexive. That is, if a relation R on a set A has the property that (a,b) in R and (b,a) in R (symmetry) and (a,b) in R and (b,c) in R implies (a,c) in R (transitivity), does it always have the property that (a,a) in R for all a in A (reflexivity)? Analysis of the definitions of these properties is necessary.
02
Construct a Counterexample
A counterexample is a specific example that refutes a statement. For the statement to be true, it must hold for all possible relations. To disprove this statement, a relation can be constructed that is symmetric and transitive, but not reflexive. Consider the relation R on the set A = {1, 2} where R = {(1,2), (2,1)}. This relation is symmetric, because if (a,b) in R then (b,a) is in R for all a,b in A. The relation is transitive because there are no elements a, b, and c in A such that (a,b) in R and (b,c) in R, but (a,c) not in R. However, it is not reflexive because there are elements a in A such that (a,a) is not in R (in this case, (1,1) and (2,2) are not in R).
03
Concluding Remarks
The relation R = {(1,2), (2,1)} on the set A = {1, 2} serves as a counterexample that disproves the statement. Thus, it is not necessarily true that a relation that is symmetric and transitive must also be reflexive.
Unlock Step-by-Step Solutions & Ace Your Exams!
-
Full Textbook Solutions
Get detailed explanations and key concepts
-
Unlimited Al creation
Al flashcards, explanations, exams and more...
-
Ads-free access
To over 500 millions flashcards
-
Money-back guarantee
We refund you if you fail your exam.
Over 30 million students worldwide already upgrade their learning with Vaia!
Key Concepts
These are the key concepts you need to understand to accurately answer the question.
Symmetry in Relations
In the context of mathematical relations, symmetry is a property that imparts a sense of balance. Specifically, if a relation \(R\) on a set \(A\) is symmetric, it means whenever a pair \( (a, b) \) is in \(R\), the pair \( (b, a) \) is also in \(R\). That is, the relationship works both ways: if \(a\) is related to \(b\), then \(b\) is also related to \(a\).
Imagine friends who have a mutual understanding to help each other; if \(a\) helps \(b\), then \(b\) must help \(a\) as well. That's the essence of symmetry in the context of relations. It's important to note, a relation can be symmetric without including every possible pair in the set—what matters is that for every pair that is included, its symmetric counterpart is also present.
Imagine friends who have a mutual understanding to help each other; if \(a\) helps \(b\), then \(b\) must help \(a\) as well. That's the essence of symmetry in the context of relations. It's important to note, a relation can be symmetric without including every possible pair in the set—what matters is that for every pair that is included, its symmetric counterpart is also present.
Transitivity in Relations
Transitivity is another property that can characterize relationships between elements of a set. For a relation \(R\) on a set \(A\), we say that \(R\) is transitive if whenever we have two pairs \( (a, b) \) and \( (b, c) \) in \(R\), we must also have the pair \( (a, c) \) in \(R\). It's like a chain link of associations—if \(a\) is connected to \(b\), and \(b\) is connected to \(c\), then transitivity demands that \(a\) must be connected to \(c\).
In practical terms, if \(a\) is taller than \(b\), and \(b\) is taller than \(c\), then transitivity indicates that \(a\) is taller than \(c\). This property helps establish order and hierarchy within a set based on the relations defined.
In practical terms, if \(a\) is taller than \(b\), and \(b\) is taller than \(c\), then transitivity indicates that \(a\) is taller than \(c\). This property helps establish order and hierarchy within a set based on the relations defined.
Reflexivity in Relations
Reflexivity in relations is akin to self-acceptance; it relates each element to itself within a set. A relation \(R\) on a set \(A\) is reflexive if each element \(a\) of \(A\) is related to itself—meaning the pair \( (a, a) \) is always in \(R\) for every element \(a\) in \(A\).
Let's use ownership as a simple illustration: if every item belongs to itself, then the relation 'belongs to' is reflexive. It automatically holds that each item is its own proprietor. In a reflexive relation, this principle of self-inclusion must apply universally to all members of the set \(A\).
Let's use ownership as a simple illustration: if every item belongs to itself, then the relation 'belongs to' is reflexive. It automatically holds that each item is its own proprietor. In a reflexive relation, this principle of self-inclusion must apply universally to all members of the set \(A\).
Counterexamples
Counterexamples are the secret weapon mathematicians use to disprove statements or conjectures. They provide a specific example or case that contradicts a general statement, thus demonstrating its invalidity. In the instance of our initial problem, we disproved the claim that symmetry and transitivity in a relation imply reflexivity by offering a counterexample—an explicit relation that is both symmetric and transitive but fails to be reflexive.
Consider our earlier relation \(R = \{ (1,2), (2,1) \}\) on the set \(A = \{1, 2\}\). It respects symmetry and transitivity, yet it does not include the pairs \( (1,1) \) and \( (2,2) \), which are obligatory for reflexivity. This single counterexample is enough to overturn the assumption that symmetry and transitivity necessitate reflexivity, highlighting the power of counterexamples in mathematical proofs.
Consider our earlier relation \(R = \{ (1,2), (2,1) \}\) on the set \(A = \{1, 2\}\). It respects symmetry and transitivity, yet it does not include the pairs \( (1,1) \) and \( (2,2) \), which are obligatory for reflexivity. This single counterexample is enough to overturn the assumption that symmetry and transitivity necessitate reflexivity, highlighting the power of counterexamples in mathematical proofs.