Warning: foreach() argument must be of type array|object, bool given in /var/www/html/web/app/themes/studypress-core-theme/template-parts/header/mobile-offcanvas.php on line 20

The CARA and CRRA utility functions are both members of a more general class of utility functions called harmonic absolute risk aversion (HARA) functions. The general form for this function is \(U(W)=\theta(\mu+W / \gamma)^{1-\gamma}\), where the various parameters obey the following restrictions: \(\bullet$$\gamma \leq 1\) \(\bullet$$\mu+W / \gamma > 0\) \(\bullet$$\theta[(1-\gamma) / \gamma] > 0\) The reasons for the first two restrictions are obvious; the third is required so that \(U^{\prime} > 0\) a. Calculate \(r(W)\) for this function. Show that the reciprocal of this expression is linear in \(W\). This is the origin of the term harmonic in the function's name. b. Show that when \(\mu=0\) and \(\theta=[(1-\gamma) / \gamma]^{\gamma-1},\) this function reduces to the CRRA function given in Chapter 7 (see footnote 17 ). c. Use your result from part (a) to show that if \(\gamma \rightarrow \infty\), then \(r(W)\) is a constant for this function. d. Let the constant found in part (c) be represented by \(A\). Show that the implied form for the utility function in this case is the CARA function given in Equation 7.35 e. Finally, show that a quadratic utility function can be generated from the HARA function simply by setting \(\gamma=-1\) f. Despite the seeming generality of the HARA function, it still exhibits several limitations for the study of behavior in uncertain situations. Describe some of these shortcomings.

Short Answer

Expert verified
Answer: Some limitations of the HARA utility function when studying behavior in uncertain situations include its inability to represent all possible risk preferences, the assumption of a specific functional form that may not accurately represent individual preferences, and the lack of capturing changes in preferences over time, which could be important for long-term decision-making.

Step by step solution

01

Calculating the first derivative of the utility function

To find absolute risk aversion, first, we need to find the first derivative of the utility function with respect to \(W\). Differentiate \(U(W)\) with respect to W: \(U^{\prime}(W)= \theta (1-\gamma)(\mu + W / \gamma)^{-\gamma}\)
02

Calculating the second derivative of the utility function

Now, we find the second derivative of the utility function with respect to \(W\): \(U^{\prime\prime}(W)= \theta (1-\gamma)\gamma (\mu + W / \gamma)^{-(\gamma+1)}\)
03

Finding \(r(W)\)

Absolute risk aversion, \(r(W)\), is defined as the ratio of the second derivative of the utility function to the first derivative. Thus, we find \(r(W)\) by dividing the second derivative by the first derivative: \(r(W) = \frac{U^{\prime\prime}(W)}{U^{\prime}(W)} = \frac{\theta (1-\gamma)\gamma (\mu + W / \gamma)^{-(\gamma+1)}}{\theta (1-\gamma)(\mu + W / \gamma)^{-\gamma}} = \frac{\gamma}{\mu+\frac{W}{\gamma}}\) As seen in the last step, the reciprocal of \(r(W)\) has the form \(aW+b\), where a and b are constants. This makes it linear in \(W\). #b. The CRRA Function#
04

Substituting values for \(\mu\) and \(\theta\)

Now we show that when \(\mu=0\) and \(\theta=[(1-\gamma) / \gamma]^{\gamma-1},\) the HARA utility function reduces to the CRRA function. Substitute these values into the HARA function \(U(W)=\theta(\mu+W/\gamma)^{1-\gamma}\): \(U(W)=\left(\frac{1-\gamma}{\gamma}\right)^{\gamma-1} (W/\gamma)^{1-\gamma}\)
05

Simplifying the utility function

Simplify the utility function by multiplying the two exponents: \(U(W) = W^{1-\gamma}\) This is the same as the CRRA utility function given in the question. #c. Constant Risk Aversion as \(\gamma \rightarrow \infty\)
06

Finding the limit of \(r(W)\)

Find the limit of the absolute risk aversion as \(\gamma\) approaches infinity: \(\lim_{\gamma \rightarrow \infty} \frac{\gamma}{\mu+\frac{W}{\gamma}}\)
07

Applying L'Hopital's rule

Using L'Hopital's rule, we find the limit: \(\lim_{\gamma \rightarrow \infty} \frac{\gamma}{\mu+\frac{W}{\gamma}} = \lim_{\gamma \rightarrow \infty} \frac{1}{\frac{-W}{\gamma^2}} = 0\) When \(\gamma \rightarrow \infty\), \(r(W)\) approaches a constant value. #d. The CARA Utility Function#
08

Setting the constant as A

Let the constant found in part (c) be represented by \(A\). Substitute this value into the HARA utility function: \(U(W)=\theta(\mu+W/\infty)^{1-\infty}\)
09

Simplifying the utility function

This simplifies to the CARA utility function: \(U(W)=-e^{-AW}\) #e. Quadratic Utility Function#
10

Setting \(\gamma=-1\)

Set \(\gamma=-1\) in the HARA utility function: \(U(W)=\theta(\mu+W/\gamma)^{1-\gamma}\)
11

Simplifying the utility function

Simplify the function by plugging in \(\gamma = -1\): \(U(W)=\theta(\mu+W/(-1))^{2}\) This is a quadratic utility function. #f. Limitations of the HARA utility function# Some limitations of the HARA utility function for the study of behavior in uncertain situations include: 1. HARA utility functions cannot represent all possible risk preferences. 2. HARA utility functions assume a specific functional form, which may not accurately represent individual preferences in all situations. 3. HARA utility functions may not capture changes in preferences over time, which could be important in the context of long-term decision-making.

Unlock Step-by-Step Solutions & Ace Your Exams!

  • Full Textbook Solutions

    Get detailed explanations and key concepts

  • Unlimited Al creation

    Al flashcards, explanations, exams and more...

  • Ads-free access

    To over 500 millions flashcards

  • Money-back guarantee

    We refund you if you fail your exam.

Over 30 million students worldwide already upgrade their learning with Vaia!

Key Concepts

These are the key concepts you need to understand to accurately answer the question.

Absolute Risk Aversion
When it comes to understanding an individual's attitude toward risk, absolute risk aversion plays a crucial role. It is a measure of how much one's satisfaction (or utility) decreases as the risk in a situation increases. In more technical terms, it is defined by the negative of the second derivative of the utility function with respect to wealth (\(W\)), divided by the first derivative of the utility function with respect to wealth.

Absolute risk aversion is critical because it shows us how risk tolerance changes with varying levels of wealth. For instance, with a high level of absolute risk aversion, a small increase in risk causes a significant reduction in utility, suggesting that the individual is risk-averse. Conversely, if absolute risk aversion is low, the individual is more tolerant of risk. This concept is reflected in the utility function's curvature: the greater the curvature, the higher the level of risk aversion.
CARA Utility Function
The Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA) utility function is a specific type of utility model where the degree of risk aversion remains the same irrespective of changes in wealth. It is a pivotal concept in economics and finance because it allows for the simple modeling of risk-averse behavior without the complexity that varying risk aversion with wealth entails.

In a typical CARA utility function, represented by the equation \(U(W)=-e^{-AW}\), the parameter \(A\) stands for the level of absolute risk aversion, and it stays constant as wealth, \(W\), changes. This implies that whether the individual is wealthy or not, their dislike for taking risks remains the same. This simplicity makes the CARA model convenient for certain economic analyses, although it may not accurately represent all individuals' behavior.
CRRA Utility Function
Contrastive to the CARA model, the Constant Relative Risk Aversion (CRRA) utility function describes a situation where an individual's risk aversion is related to their relative wealth position, not the absolute amount. Here, the individual’s dislike for risk is constant in percentage terms.

The CRRA utility function, which is given by \(U(W) = W^{1-\gamma}\), where \(\gamma\) is the coefficient of relative risk aversion, is particularly useful for describing behaviors where the individual's risk aversion changes alongside proportional changes in wealth. For example, if a person's wealth doubles, their risk aversion in terms of proportional wealth remains unchanged. CRRA models are widely used in financial studies because they offer a more realistic depiction of how people's risk preferences might vary with different levels of wealth.
Risk Preferences
Risk preferences are at the core of financial decision-making, guiding how individuals make choices under uncertainty. They define an individual’s willingness to take or avoid risk and are shaped by psychological factors, economic circumstances, and even cultural background.

Understanding an individual's risk preferences is crucial for predicting behavior in financial markets, personal savings, insurance, and investment decisions. They are deeply ingrained characteristics that influence how a person perceives the trade-off between the potential for higher returns and the willingness to accept the associated risks. Economists categorize risk preferences into three primary types: risk-averse (preferring certainty over gamble for the same expected return), risk-neutral (indifferent between certainty and gamble), and risk-seeking (preferring the gamble over certainty). Each of these preferences can be mathematically described by specific types of utility functions, which help in constructing financial models and theories.

One App. One Place for Learning.

All the tools & learning materials you need for study success - in one app.

Get started for free

Most popular questions from this chapter

Investment in risky assets can be examined in the state-preference framework by assuming that \(W^{*}\) dollars invested in an asset with a certain return \(r\) will yield \(W^{*}(1+r)\) in both states of the world, whereas investment in a risky asset will yield \(W^{+}\left(1+r_{g}\right)\) in good times and \(W^{*}\left(1+r_{b}\right)\) in bad times (where \(r_{g}>r>r_{b}\) ). a. Graph the outcomes from the two investments. b. Show how a "mixed portfolio" containing both risk-free and risky assets could be illustrated in your graph. How would you show the fraction of wealth invested in the risky asset? c. Show how individuals' attitudes toward risk will determine the mix of risk- free and risky assets they will hold. In what case would a person hold no risky assets? d. If an individual's utility takes the constant relative risk aversion form (Equation 7.42 ), explain why this person will not change the fraction of risky assets held as his or her wealth increases. \(^{25}\)

In deciding to park in an illegal place, any individual knows that the probability of getting a ticket is \(p\) and that the fine for receiving the ticket is \(f\). Suppose that all individuals are risk averse (i.e., \(U^{\prime \prime}(W)<0\), where \(W\) is the individual's wealth). Will a proportional increase in the probability of being caught or a proportional increase in the fine be a more effective deterrent to illegal parking? Hint: Use the Taylor series approximation \(U(W-f)=U(W)-f U^{\prime}(W)+\left(f^{2} / 2\right) U^{\prime \prime}(W)\)

An individual purchases a dozen eggs and must take them home. Although making trips home is costless, there is a 50 percent chance that all the eggs carried on any one trip will be broken during the trip. The individual considers two strategies: (1) take all 12 eggs in one trip; or (2) take two trips with 6 eggs in each trip. a. List the possible outcomes of each strategy and the probabilities of these outcomes. Show that, on average, 6 eggs will remain unbroken after the trip home under either strategy. b. Develop a graph to show the utility obtainable under each strategy. Which strategy will be preferable? c. Could utility be improved further by taking more than two trips? How would this possibility be affected if additional trips were costly?

Return to Example \(7.5,\) in which we computed the value of the real option provided by a flexible-fuel car. Continue to assume that the payoff from a fossil-fuel-burning car is \(A_{1}(x)=1-x\). Now assume that the payoff from the biofuel car is higher, \(A_{2}(x)=2 x\). As before, \(x\) is a random variable uniformly distributed between 0 and 1 , capturing the relative availability of biofuels versus fossil fuels on the market over the future lifespan of the car. a. Assume the buyer is risk neutral with von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function \(U(x)=x\). Compute the option value of a flexible-fuel car that allows the buyer to reproduce the payoff from either single-fuel car. b. Repeat the option value calculation for a risk-averse buyer with utility function \(U(x)=\sqrt{x}\) c. Compare your answers with Example \(7.5 .\) Discuss how the increase in the value of the biofuel car affects the option value provided by the flexible- fuel car.

Two pioneers of the field of behavioral economics, Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (winners of the Nobel Prize in economics in 2002 , conducted an experiment in which they presented different groups of subjects with one of the following two scenarios: Scenario 1: In addition to \(\$ 1,000\) up front, the subject must choose between two gambles. Gamble \(A\) offers an even chance of winning \(\$ 1,000\) or nothing. Gamble \(B\) provides \(\$ 500\) with certainty. Scenario 2: In addition to \(\$ 2,000\) given up front, the subject must choose between two gambles. Gamble \(C\) offers an even chance of losing \(\$ 1,000\) or nothing. Gamble \(D\) results in the loss of \(\$ 500\) with certainty. a. Suppose Standard Stan makes choices under uncertainty according to expected utility theory. If Stan is risk neutral, what choice would he make in each scenario? b. What choice would Stan make if he is risk averse? c. Kahneman and Tversky found 16 percent of subjects chose \(A\) in the first scenario and 68 percent chose \(C\) in the second scenario. Based on your preceding answers, explain why these findings are hard to reconcile with expected utility theory. d. Kahneman and Tversky proposed an alternative to expected utility theory, called prospect theory, to explain the experimental results. The theory is that people's current income level functions as an "anchor point" for them. They are risk averse over gains beyond this point but sensitive to small losses below this point. This sensitivity to small losses is the opposite of risk aversion: \(A\) risk-averse person suffers disproportionately more from a large than a small loss. (1) Prospect Pete makes choices under uncertainty according to prospect theory. What choices would he make in Kahneman and Tversky's experiment? Explain. (2) Draw a schematic diagram of a utility curve over money for Prospect Pete in the first scenario. Draw a utility curve for him in the second scenario. Can the same curve suffice for both scenarios, or must it shift? How do Pete's utility curves differ from the ones we are used to drawing for people like Standard \(\operatorname{Stan} ?\)

See all solutions

Recommended explanations on Economics Textbooks

View all explanations

What do you think about this solution?

We value your feedback to improve our textbook solutions.

Study anywhere. Anytime. Across all devices.

Sign-up for free